Banner Advertiser

Sunday, September 30, 2007

[vinnomot] 1st Reunion of Public Administration Alumni Association, University of Chittagong

Dear Alumni,
We are very pleased to inform you that Public Administration Alumni Association (PAAA), University of Chittagong is going to celebrate its 1st reunion which will take place on 9 November 2007 at the king of Chittagong community center, Panchliash, Chittagong.  It will be a day long program. All ex-student of Public Administration, University of Chittagong are requested to get your membership and registration for reunion. Our website (http://www.paaacu.org) is already started in test basis and finally it will be launching in this occasion. Membership form is available in our website and you will also find registration form very shortly. A draft schedule of program is enclosed.
Further details:
Please Contact:
 
Md. Zahed Hasan Saimon
Member
Registration Sub Committee
&
Coordinator
Media & Communication
Public Administration Alumni Association, University of Chittagong
Cell: +88-01716498248
We anticipate your all out cooperation in this regard and looking forward to seeing you soon.
 
Thanks and best regards.
 
Zahed


Building a website is a piece of cake.
Yahoo! Small Business gives you all the tools to get online. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Fwd: [notun_bangladesh] Re: STATEMENT ON ARIFUR RAHMAN from CFI Internationa...

 
__._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Here is a reason for which CTG can justify banning Jamat-e-Islami

Here is a reason for which CTG can justify banning Jamat-e-Islami

The corrupt politics of the two main parties and the hollowness in the personalities of the leaders (leftists or center) - these were the lifeline and these still are the life-blood for the politics of Jamat. Moreover, our two national fools - Dr. K. and Dr. B. brought in the two ladies from their 'heshel' to lead their respective parties, in the name of unity and eventually to destroy what was still left of politics in Bangladesh. Although, the two ladies are paying the prices, punishing the people who surrounded them is more needed. The cunning Go.A. and his party has so far maximized their political gain from this political hodgepodge because of these big mistakes perpetrated by our national leaders, their corrupt character or for the lack of strength in their statesman approach to leadership.Its time to think about possible correction.

So what? Somebody has taken advantage of the situation prevalent in the environment. At least, Go.A. and his party knew how to read the environment and make use of it, isn't it? Now that those fools and stupids are realizing that they have nothing to be proud of, they have achieved very little and many of them are lining up to prepare themselves in jails, they are doing their last thing - express their hate towards the party of Go.A. on the basis of something which they could not do or at the least, did not think doable. Now, they are demanding this out of CTG, with the hope (in their heart) to belittle this fledgling government - to create pressure on the CTG to get out of corruption fight prematurely or at least, to save their faces. What more harm can you do, dear politicians? Can't you just say "Dhoroni Dhidha Hou"!! and leave us, the people, alone?

Moreover, the basis or logic on which many of these stupids are writing their tune, is a faulty one. What do you do - if the younger generation leadership within that party - who probably have nothing wrong to do during 1971, if they sideline all the senior party leaders (say, who are above 45 years of age) from leadership? At least, they do not have to get their leaders ordered out of mother's womb! They practice democracy - whatever the word 'democracy' mean to them. But they don't order their leaders from a certain factory, they create their own leaders, isn't it? But lets not go there for today, lets focus on the topic.

We would imagine, there are many in line who can take over and will take over from those who allegedly did wrong during 1971. This particular allegation is confusing to the new generation people (at least to many of them who likes to think themselves as rational and open minded). Because nobody thought of filing cases against them, let alone arresting them during last 36 years. Well, except only Jahanara Imam's Gono-Adalot. Many of the nation participated in that practice and the verdict of that trial is declared already. That court is given its verdict and it is a close deal as far as that particular court is concerned. But that form of justice is supposed to inform the public - which it did successfully - to some extant.

 

Coming back to the issue - so, is there anything to do for the CTG about this issue? Or rather, could there be a ground or justification for the CTG to consider action against Jamat? Let us analyze. And it seems yes, only after, if the leadership in CTG thinks the govt. has been successful to cut the bloodline for the Jamatis or for that matter, the bloodline for any fundamentalist politics. Once that is done, action can be two-fold. State can take a legal position against these culprit - if there is a legal ground (ICC comes to mind), and also, the State can take a moral position on this matter - that has to be clearly positioned and succinctly articulated. Not like some of those Zillul / Menon / Inu type politicians would like it to be articulated.

 

How should CTG decide that it has done enough to cut the bloodline for the Jamati-type politics? Here is a benchmark. Out of the 222 listed, there should be at least 100 hard-core corrupt who would not accept the responsibility and wouldn't plea guilty. But there would be another hundred or so, who would like to plead guilty and want to cooperate with the government - in return of a peaceful private (not public) life with less punishment. Government should use those hundred or so to get others who were not listed or could not be listed. Those others will be implicated by these hundred pleading guilty. On the average if one corrupt gives enough information to get another 10 fishes.... that gives the government about 1000 new corrupts to work with. Again among those 1000 new, they will probably eventually find about 500 hardcore corrupts who should be sent behind bar for at least 15 years each or for life. Also, if the ACC takes its time to continue this kind of work in a iterative way - that should make sure that Bangladesh would come out of vicious cycle of corruption on the national scale - in a few years time. But is ACC to completely equipped yet for that kind of work? No, we do not think so. Government should take RAB - detach it from regular police force - and attach it with the ACC permanently. RAB should become the action arm of ACC - the size of RAB should be smaller in size but flexible in that the ACC Chairman can co-opt any number of members temporarily from various government agencies (NBR, BoI, Army, Police, Navy, BCS, etc) or private companies or NGOs as needed basis. It will be a true reflection of its name - RAP ACTION BATTALION.

Anyways, coming back to the topic - once that is done, govt should have a reasonable comfort that the bloodline of Jamat has been cut off. Now, dealing with the fundamentalists will be a one time job. If the aforementioned thing is not done first, the dealing with the fundamentalists will not be a one time job, rather targeting the Jamatis will enhance their popularity - since they might be seen as victimized and get popularity since the general people dis-like other corrupts even more. Moreover, you have to take into consideration that the population are poor and lacks proper eduction. But if we have blown off the corrupts from the major parties and from the bureaucracy, and also placed a mechanism that this cleansing up will continue to make sure that things will not reverse, rather things should improve over time. That would make sure that anti-Jamat action would not backfire.

So, let us assume every pre-condition has been achieved. Now, what the CTG can do?

Going back to our allegation of AL/BNP that they could not or did not go after Jamat - CTG should ask the same question themselves. If they could not go after Jamat, why? (A) Was it lack of competence or (B) Was it lack of political will? or (C) Was it because there is not a case, actually? or (D) Is it the other case - AL/BNP did not go after Jamat even though they could go after them?

Out of these four options, only if (C) is found to be true, CTG can avoid the duty of going after Jamat. We are not sure, what CTG can do in that case. But, if it was the case of either (A) or (B) or (D) - which our so called politicians should clarify - the CTG can not avoid the responsibility of doing something about Jamat. They should and we think, they would do something when the time is proper. But that process should start with a dialogue with all the traditional party leaders articulating their reason for not doing anything so far. That should be made public. Once a consensus is reached about the reason - articulated by the political leaders, the eradication of fundamentalist politics from Bangladesh would be a matter of time. And the CTG can at least initiate the task, if not complete it, given the time crunch that it has. Or may be, it can ask for more time to complete this additional job, after completing the jobs at hand.

If you thought some of the ideas are worth of your reading time, please forward it to others. If you have an ear to the members of CTG, leaders of the political parties and activists, members of the civil soceity and legal organizations, please forward it to them. If you have an ear to the journalists and news editors of the electronic media, discuss it with them. Hope they would look at the suggestions and give due diligence.

Thanks for your time,

Innovation Line

==================================================================================================

Note: This is a freelance column, published mainly in different internet based forums. This column is open for contribution by the members of new generation, sometimes referred to as Gen 71. If you identify yourself as someone from that age-group and want to contribute to this column, please feel free to contact. Thanks to the group moderator for publishing the article.

We have not seen the Liberation War, but we know if we can free the country from corruption first, we will eventually get to other dreams soon. Because of corruption, we could not even get into information highway for years, let alone other dreams!

This is the kind of article for which we started this column. Because of ongoing mess, a gift from our older generation, we often get diverted. Now that it seems some sanity is returning in Bangladesh, we would try to go back to our original plan.

==================================================================================================

__._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Latest casualty of Military beating, Victim's family seek justice from god

Victim's family seeking justice from God indicates that a society, without human justice, is being run by armed bandits, trampling the individual rights and disregarding the value of human lives.
 
links:
Is this a crime against humanity or casualty of war against corruption? How long does such action must go on? Will the pepetrators be ever brought to justice?
 
Will this death, like any other death in Military custody and from beating by military perssonels in past, be unaccounted for and perpetrators go unpunshied?
 
How is this different from the last five-year of misrule of BNP-Jaamat coalition?
 
 
Sadly,
 
Nasir
 
 
 
 
 


ABM Nasir, Ph.D.
Assistant Professor and Lead Faculty of Economics
School of Business
NCCU Campus NRC Director,
North Carolina Center for South Asian Studies
North Carolina Central Univeristy
Durham, NC 27707.
Phone: (919) 530-7372
Fax: (919) 530-6163
http://www.nccu.edu/business/anasir


Yahoo! oneSearch: Finally, mobile search that gives answers, not web links. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Fwd: Genocide Studies on Bangladesh at Kean University



Note: forwarded message attached.


Got a little couch potato?
Check out fun summer activities for kids. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

Re: [ALOCHONA] CTG - tottaly failed ,even in anti-corruption drive .

I don't think putting them in jail will solve the
problem. They may take china's treatment for crime
against the nation.

Treat them like Bangla Bhai. Bring fear to criminals
heart.

--- halder <johalder@hotmail.com> wrote:

>
> Their big fail is, yet they could not make money
> by corruption !
> Is't it dear?
>
>
> ----- Original Message -----
> From: mahathir of bd
> To: alochona@yahoogroups.com
> Sent: Friday, September 28, 2007 8:40 AM
> Subject: [ALOCHONA] CTG - tottaly failed ,even
> in anti-corruption drive .
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
> CTG, once popular and supported by majority
> of bangladeshi, has totally failed.
>
> It has failed
>
> 1. to Bring down price spiral of essentials
>
> 2. to create any new job
>
> 3. to control inflation
>
> 4. to bring foreign investment
>
> 5. increase export of garments
>
> 6. to keep up the GDP
>
> 7. to supply enough fertilizer to farmer
>
> 8 . to keep up the development work and
> productivity of different sector.
>
>
> 9. to reform the political parties
>
> 10. to form political party by Yunus,
> Quraesy.
>
> Do you need any more failure?
>
> Yes, big failure is yet to be brought
> before you.
>
>
> they even failed to bring down corruption.
> Bangladesh 's score in the CPI is the same as it
> was last year during BNP rule. After becoming
> champion in 2001, bangladesh increased its score
> in CPI every year.
>
> But this year it has not increased. it is
> the same 2 as it was last year.
>
> So what is the result of these six months
> intensive anti-corruption drive?
> BIGGGGGGGGGGG Zero
> (As some new countries has entered in the CPI
> index and corruption in some countries have
> increased, Bangladesh has got seventh position)
>
>
> the anti-corruption drive is about to finish.
> So is there any probability of decrease of
> corruption in Bangladesh y this CTG?
>
>
>
> If not then what is their moral ground to
> remain in power and delay the election?
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
>
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
> Subhan Allah- Only Allah flawless
> Alhamdulillah - All praise to be of
> Allah
> Allahhuakbar - Allah, the
> Greatest
>
>
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------Would
> Be Mahathir of BD
>
>
------------------------------------------------------------------
> If it can be imagined, it is possible- NEC
>
>
>
>
--------------------------------------------------------------------------
> Be a better Heartthrob. Get better
> relationship answers from someone who knows.
> Yahoo! Answers - Check it out.
>
>
>
>
>
>
---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
> Subhan Allah- Only Allah flawless
> Alhamdulillah - All praise to be of
> Allah
> Allahhuakbar - Allah, the
> Greatest
>
>
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------Would
> Be Mahathir of BD
>
>
------------------------------------------------------------------
> If it can be imagined, it is possible- NEC
>
>
>
>
>
----------------------------------------------------------------------------
> Fussy? Opinionated? Impossible to please?
> Perfect. Join Yahoo!'s user panel and lay it on us.
>
>
>
>
>


http://www.geocities.com/jamilspic


[Disclaimer: ALOCHONA Management is not liable for information contained in this message. The author takes full responsibility.]
To unsubscribe/subscribe, send request to alochona-owner@egroups.com
Yahoo! Groups Links

<*> To visit your group on the web, go to:

http://groups.yahoo.com/group/alochona/

<*> Your email settings:
Individual Email | Traditional

<*> To change settings online go to:

http://groups.yahoo.com/group/alochona/join

(Yahoo! ID required)

<*> To change settings via email:
mailto:alochona-digest@yahoogroups.com
mailto:alochona-fullfeatured@yahoogroups.com

<*> To unsubscribe from this group, send an email to:
alochona-unsubscribe@yahoogroups.com

<*> Your use of Yahoo! Groups is subject to:

http://docs.yahoo.com/info/terms/

[vinnomot] Humanism and Psychology: (Introdution 1): Scientific Psychology

 
Understanding Ourselves and Our Universe: How Psychology Can Turn the "Mysteries of Human Nature" into Useful Tools for Self Improvement and Success in Life
 
Part 1: An introduction to Scientific Psychology
An old song says, "Oh sweet mystery of life, at last I've found you." If true, that was one fortunate songwriter! For throughout the long history of our species, humans have naturally sought answers to the mysteries in their lives -- both sweet and sour -- but, until quite recently, without much success. In this Introductory Module, we will first explain what we mean by scientific psychology ("SciPsy"), what alternative approaches have been used to try to understand human psychology (and with what success), and why scientific methods have proven best. After previewing the basic principles of "SciPsy", we'll end this module by introducing some scientific laws and principles that you can use to understand and answer questions about human psychology (with each subsequent Module providing even better answers, in ever greater depth and breadth).
In a practical sense, all people are students of psychology, since understanding why we think, feel, and act as we do is an integral part of developing into successful adults. But for over 99% of the history of humankind, there was no real science of human psychology; thus, valid insights into the true causes for human nature were rare. From the first time millions of years ago that a humanoid thought, "Why did I [or someone else] do that?" or "...think that?" or "...feel that way?" -- humans have tried to understand themselves and others, but up until the late 19th and 20th centuries ; except the insight of Buddha's insight during his enlightenment experience, and other such insights in ancient Greek philosophers, Chines under Confucis, Iranian Zorothasht, ancient Indians as in Vedas and in other ancient and medieval  philosophers ; there were very few insights and even in these cases there were poor investigative tools and theories to do so accurately.
All that changed with two historic events which were possible by the humanist Enlightenment's great work of freeing human mind, particularly in Europe, from the religious shackles of Christianity; these were the publication of Charles Darwin's The Origin of Species in England in 1859 (which firmly placed humans as the most developed and dignified of the animal kingdom, and opened human study to the more sophisticated scientific techniques already developed for investigating non-humans, which had earlier been refused on the name of religion), and the founding of the first laboratory for the systematic study of human psychology by William Wundt (photo), the "Father of Scientific Psychology," in Leipzig, Germany in 1879. Our understanding of humans has simply not been the same since.
Despite these two great breakthroughs, it has only been within the last half of the 20th century that truly scientific psychology has taken hold. The previous thousands of years of "unscientific psychology" were marked by what some now call "black box psychology." That is, even after we knew that psychological phenomena were centered in the brain (while ancient texts had located all important psychological functions in the heart), due to powerful technical, social, ethical, religious, and legal constraints we were unable to "see inside" to study the brain directly.
It was as if the key object of psychological research was locked away in an inaccessible, unviewable, "black box ", in some dark religious  building. Thus, the study of psychology branched into two general research approaches; proto-scientific : (using the objective empirical means then available to slowly build credible evidence of the brain's functions and dysfunctions), and non-scientific: (using primarily subjective means to form hypotheses about the causes and effects of human psychological phenomena).
This distinction between scientific and unscientific psychology is vital to our discussuion. A valid and useful understanding of human psychology is primarily a function of the quality of our knowledge, which is in turn primarily a function of the quality of the evidence we have, which in turn is primarily a function of the quality of the methodology used to gather that evidence. There are millions of wrong answers out there, and relatively few right answers!
To repeat for emphasis, when it comes to answering key questions about human psychology, the best methods yield the best evidence of the natural principles and laws that govern human psychology. That best evidence -- properly analyzed, interpreted, and formed into theories -- produces the best knowledge and understanding of why humans think, feel, and behave as we do.
The scientific method, in brief, is a means of explaining and predicting cause and effect. In psychology, the effects are always some human thought, feeling, or behavior, or combination thereof. When someone's thought, feeling, or behavior is observed, the scientific method is the best means of answering the "why" questions; e.g., Why does Aunt Maud drink so much alcohol? Why can I love someone I don't even like? What motivated the terrorists in the World Trade Center and Pentagon attacks? Why are some people highly intelligent, while others are not? Why are some people humanists, but others are not? What are the key causes that determine why most people act as they do? That means we research the cause(s) -- i.e., the independent variable(s)-- of each effect, so we can better understand (explain and predict) what causes that effect, and better influence and even control that effect in the future for the benefit of the person and other people. In psychology, an application of the scientific method might look something like this:
In the "Maud's drinking" example :
first the scientific method operationally defines and measures the quality and quantity of her drinking behaviors. (What does she drink? When? How? How much? What precipitates her drinking? What are the consequences?) This process generates a list of possible causes of Maud's drinking, as well as a list of the possible consequences of that drinking behavior.
Second, scientists form causal hypotheses -- based on that causal list and their prior knowledge of these kinds of evidence. (Since causes must always precede effects, which of the already identified precipitating events, or any other known precipitating events, are the most likely causes of Maud's drinking behaviors?) In this example, let's say that we determine that most of Maud's drinking seems to be correlated with three precipitating events: being alone, being depressed, and instances of family conflict.
Third, those causal hypotheses are rigorously tested -- by research design and statistical analysis techniques -- to determine not only whether one or more of the hypothesized causes really accounts for the observed results, but exactly to what extent the results are accounted for by those causes. (Do our causal hypotheses account for most of the observed results -- maybe 70% or even 90%, or more? -- or do they only account for 50% of the results, or 20%, or even less?) Let's say that "aloneness" doesn't account for much of Maud's drinking -- i.e., she drinks as frequently in the presence of others as she does by herself -- but instances of depression account for ~85% of her drinking.
Fourth, if most of the effect's causes have been identified statistically, we proceed to experimental testing. We subject Maud and/or other drinkers like Maud to carefully controlled experiments on each cause, each effect, and each consequence of Maud's drinking behaviors and the result of the observation is called replication.
5th. The two forms of replication are called direct replication and systematic replication, respectively.) Replication tells us whether our original findings are real, and to what kinds of drinking, and what kinds of people, and what kinds of consequences we can apply our results. For example, we might find that both depression and family conflicts are real causes of drinking behaviors, but depression is much less of a factor for young drinkers, and that family conflicts are much less of a factor for elderly alcoholics living alone. We might also find that the primary consequences of such drinking behavior are worsened depression, more family conflicts, and several additional health problems.
Finally, Step 6 of the scientific method is to take our cause:effect results from these studies and do three things with them: (1) Disseminate these results to the scientific psychology community for critical review and comment. (2) Integrate these results into current theories of the causes and consequences of alcohol drinking, and modify those theories accordingly. And (3), perhaps most importantly, apply these results to therapeutic interventions for Maud and people like Maud with drinking problems.
Step 7 is to follow up on Maud's and similar people's treatments to see how effective they are (using what are called efficacy studies). This same method could have been applied to the other examples above, or any other aspect of human cognition, emotion, or behavior. Only when such rigorous research into the causes and consequences of some human psychological phenomena is accomplished, followed up with systematic and thorough statistical analyses, experimentation, and replication, and then followed through with treatment hypotheses, testing, and efficacy studies, can the best answers to psychological cause and effect questions be found. The strength of science is in its methodology. Only the scientific method goes to these great lengths of rigor, objectivity, thoroughness, and follow-through in search of answers; no other method comes close! (Once completed, others can use these results without going back through all these steps.)
Thus, scientific methods are best because they are the most rigorous, objective, systematic, thorough, testable, verifiable, replicable, and self-correcting ways to investigate anything! (The best aspects of all the methods of gaining knowledge ever used in the history of our species have thus been boiled down to their best elements, and combined into what we now call the scientific method.) Likewise, unscientific methods are inferior because they produce unnecessary errors (e.g., more "false positives" -- leading people to believe something that isn't true -- and "false negatives" -- not believing something that is true). Unscientific methods lead to unreliable evidence and invalid "understandings" because they are often haphazardly done, subjective, unsystematic, incomplete, untestable, unverifiable, and not replicable. Unscientific methods lead to more and more serious errors of fact. Poor methodology leads to unreliable evidence, invalid knowledge, and false understandings. Wrong understandings lead to wrong decisions about what's best to do, and the more important the issue about which those decisions are made, the greater the damage such errors of understanding and decision-making can produce.
Unfortunately, just because unscientific information and theories are neither valid nor useful, that doesn't mean they aren't useful or popular, especially among the more scientifically illiterate, less knowledgeable, and more gullible members of the public, including celebrities, social leaders, and political officials. One of humanism's and humanity's biggest problems is overcoming the invalid "knowledge," misleading propaganda, and bad decisions based on supernatural and paranormal beliefs -- which we may call "dangerous nonsense" -- so widely advocated by powerful people and factions in America, Asia and other religious and backward  societies today. By many measures, the U.S. is the most superstitious, religious, and mentally backward society in the modern europeanized world, and we pay a high price for those false beliefs every day.
While there are many factors that distinguish between scientific and unscientific theories in psychology. That distinction is between two types of hypothetical constructs; empirical constructs and non-empirical constructs.
Hypothetical constructs are agents or factors that are hypothesized (guessed) to cause one or more aspects of human cognition, emotion, or behavior. These are "educated guesses" as to what might determine some aspect of human psychology, and they are called "hypothetical" because they are based on evidence. All scientific theories are built through successively better and better hypothetical constructs, and they are a necessary part of the hypothesis generating and testing process of the scientific method.
1. Empirical means real, tangible, observable, and testable. Thus, empirical constructs (ECs) are hypothetical constructs based on real evidence, and which eventually can be tangibly defined, observed, and measured using the scientific method. (Just as importantly, incorrect empirical constructs can eventually be non-verified, proven not to be true causal agents, and thus discarded by the scientific method.) (This is one important reason why the scientific method is self-correcting.)
On the other hand, non-empirical constructs (NECs) are hypothetical constructs that -- intentionally or unintentionally -- cannot be tangibly defined, observed, measured, or tested. They are in every meaningful sense unreal, like a figment of someone's imagination. Not surprisingly, such NECs do not lend themselves to objective testing, or disproof. NECs' glaring weaknesses are that they can never be ordinarily proven true, and cannot generally contribute to valid understandings or make useful predictions, and thus have no scientific use. (For naive or unscrupulous theorists and believers, however, NECs can also never be proven to be untrue). Psychology students and humanists can take no greater step forward in their understanding and development than to learn the difference between theories based on valid, useful, empirical constructs, and those based on invalid non-empirical constructs.
Just because we are advocating science to you as by far the best means to answer questions about human psychology -- or any other natural phenomena -- we must also note that science, unlike religions, is also very careful and conservative in its claims. Science never claims to have the "final answer" or "total truth" because there is always the possibility -- no matter how small -- that some as yet undiscovered law of nature will intervene, and the best scientific knowledge of today will be disproven tomorrow. For example, five hundred years ago most scientists didn't believe in meteorites. According to the Newtonian physics of that day, stones were too heavy to be up in the air, so how could they fall out of the air?! Of course, meteorites are real (the black sacred stone in Allah's House in Mecca, Arabia, « Sang-e-Aswad » is a metorite), but they are subject to natural laws of weightlessness in space unknown to scientists of that day, and the ancient Bedouins of Arabia.
Similarly, up until the 20th century, many taught that a terrible form of psychosis called general paresis was « God or Allah's punishment for "wantonness," because many of its victims led promiscuous lives ». Through scientific study, it was shown that general paresis was caused by syphilitic infections reaching and damaging the brain. So while the scientific explanation still carried a warning regarding unprotected sex, it wasn't supportive of the "God's or Allah's wrath" hypothesis. (Just as science doesn't support many religionists' claims that AIDS is "God or Allah's wrath" against very loose sexual morals.) In fact, one of psychology's greatest achievements in the 20th century has been finding the natural, organic causes for psychopathologies (diseases which effect brain and show themselves in psychological ways( that were previously believed to have been "functional" (of unknown, non-physical causes).
So even though science provides the best answers to any question, its answers are cautiously stated in probabilities or confidence levels; e.g., "We're 95% [or 99%+] confident that this answer is correct." Ironically, other less rigorous methods of answering questions are much less likely to be correct, yet they paradoxically claim to be the "absolute truth." Theistic religion, for example, claims to answer questions by "supernatural revelation" or "sacred dogma or faith" -- and cries "blasphemy" or "heresy" if anyone dares to question those flawed answers -- but it can almost never provide logical reasons or credible evidence to prove its claims. Unlike science, most religious answers are not falsifiable; i.e., they are conceptualized and stated using supernatural terms and non-empirical constructs (i.e., imaginary causal variables) for the specific purpose of not being testable. In fact, when religionists provide testable and disprovable explanations or predictions, they are usually proven to be wrong! Thus when their explanations or predictions fail -- as they routinely do -- religionists simply make up another hypothetical construct to try to explain the failures away. This "circular reasoning" leads nowhere, but it is highly valued by religionists because it is technically not disprovable by science.
Given a choice between the hard won "best answers" provided by science, or easier but functionally sterile answers by "mystical or religious" means, we should choose science every time!  
 


Got a little couch potato?
Check out fun summer activities for kids. __._,_.___


SPONSORED LINKS
Pop rock music

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Fwd: RE: A poem you might like

A Bangla Poem by Belal Beg
 


Be a better Globetrotter. Get better travel answers from someone who knows.
Yahoo! Answers - Check it out. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

Re: [ALOCHONA] CTG - tottaly failed ,even in anti-corruption drive .

 When any one is in power, you can not know it. after they have gone from power, you will know it.
 


halder <johalder@hotmail.com> wrote:
 
Their big fail is, yet they could not make money by corruption !
Is't it dear?
 
 
----- Original Message -----
Sent: Friday, September 28, 2007 8:40 AM
Subject: [ALOCHONA] CTG - tottaly failed ,even in anti-corruption drive .




  CTG,  once popular and supported by majority of bangladeshi,  has  totally failed.
 
 It has failed
 
1.  to Bring down price spiral of essentials
 
2.  to create any new job
 
3.  to control inflation
 
4.  to  bring foreign investment
 
5.  increase  export of garments
 
6.  to keep up the GDP
 
7. to supply enough fertilizer to farmer
 
8 . to keep up the development work and productivity of different sector.
 
 
9.  to reform the  political parties
 
10.  to  form political party by  Yunus, Quraesy.
 
 Do you need any more failure?
 
 Yes, big failure  is yet to  be brought before you.
 
 
they even failed to bring down corruption.  Bangladesh 's score  in the CPI  is the same as it was last year during BNP rule. After becoming  champion  in 2001, bangladesh  increased its score in CPI every year.
 
But this year  it has not increased. it is  the same  2 as it was last year.
 
 So what is the result of these six months  intensive anti-corruption drive?
BIGGGGGGGGGGG  Zero
(As some new  countries has entered in the CPI index and corruption in some countries have increased, Bangladesh has got seventh position)
 
 
 the anti-corruption drive is about to finish. So is there any  probability  of  decrease of corruption in Bangladesh y this CTG?
 
 
 
 If  not then what is their moral ground  to remain in power and delay the election?
 
 
 


---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Subhan Allah-  Only Allah flawless 
           Alhamdulillah - All praise to be of Allah 
                   Allahhuakbar - Allah, the Greatest
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------Would Be Mahathir of BD
------------------------------------------------------------------
If it can be imagined, it is possible- NEC


Be a better Heartthrob. Get better relationship answers from someone who knows.
Yahoo! Answers - Check it out.



---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Subhan Allah-  Only Allah flawless 
           Alhamdulillah - All praise to be of Allah 
                   Allahhuakbar - Allah, the Greatest
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------Would Be Mahathir of BD
------------------------------------------------------------------
If it can be imagined, it is possible- NEC


Fussy? Opinionated? Impossible to please? Perfect. Join Yahoo!'s user panel and lay it on us.

Upgrade Your Email - Click here!



---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------
Subhan Allah-  Only Allah flawless 
           Alhamdulillah - All praise to be of Allah 
                   Allahhuakbar - Allah, the Greatest
-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------Would Be Mahathir of BD
------------------------------------------------------------------
If it can be imagined, it is possible- NEC


Need a vacation? Get great deals to amazing places on Yahoo! Travel. __._,_.___

[Disclaimer: ALOCHONA Management is not liable for information contained in this message. The author takes full responsibility.]
To unsubscribe/subscribe, send request to alochona-owner@egroups.com




Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Nigeria Polio Vaccine Fiasco. Authorities Blame Undervaccination.

"Nigeria finds polio cases linked to vaccine viruses"
Updated Fri. Sep. 28 2007 8:11 AM ET
The Canadian Press

Nigeria has found 69 cases of children paralyzed by polio not caused by wild polio viruses, but rather weakened viruses from polio vaccine that have circulated and regained their power to cause disease, a team of international scientists reported Thursday.

The ongoing outbreak in northern Nigeria, which started in 2005, is also responsible for two cases of polio in neighbouring Niger, the scientists reported in Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Review, a journal published by the U.S. Centers for Disease Control.

The article details polio cases that trace back to circulating vaccine viruses, one of the major wild-cards in the labouring international effort to eradicate polio.

Such vaccine-linked outbreaks have occurred before. But this one has the potential to pose a serious threat to the polio eradication effort because of its location. Several states in Northern Nigeria suspended polio immunization efforts for nearly a year in 2003-04 in response to vaccine safety rumours that led parents to refuse to have their children immunized.

"Given the situation in Nigeria antecedent to where we are, this could be frightening, " Dr. Oyewale Tomori, vice-chancellor of Redeemer's University in Redemption City, Nigeria, admitted in an interview at a recent international polio symposium in Washington, where the cases were discussed.

Tomori, a former World Health Organization official, said if information on the cases isn't conveyed in context in Nigeria, "it could set the immunization program backwards."
The context he referred to is the fact that vaccine-derived polio virus cases - known in the shorthand of polio as VDPVs - are the result of low immunization rates in the places where they occur.

"VDPVs have occurred in many countries. And they occur when (vaccine) coverage is low. And this is a reflection of low vaccination coverage of Type 2 vaccine in Nigeria," Dr. David Heymann, the WHO official who heads the polio eradication program, said from Geneva.
The polio eradication program is a partnership between the WHO, the CDC, UNICEF and Rotary International. Begun in 1988, the program has spent more than US$5.3 billion in the so-far elusive bid to eliminate polio, a formerly ubiquitous virus that causes crippling disease in one out of every 200 people it infects.

While they acknowledge the sensitivity of the topic, a number of polio experts are dismayed the outbreak has taken so long to come to light. They've been hearing about the cases for months, through contacts and back channels.

"This has been going on for more than a year and a half and we have nothing at all about it until now? If we're this concerned about the VDPVs, let the information become public," Dr. D.A. Henderson, the infectious diseases expert who led the successful smallpox eradication program, said from Baltimore, Md.

Expert opinion is divided over the danger posed by VDPVs. The WHO insists the transmission chains formed by these viruses are easier to break than those created by wild polio viruses. Others believe these viruses, if left unchecked, will become every bit as dangerous as wild polio viruses.

The report details vaccine-derived outbreaks or individual cases in Cambodia, Myanmar, China, Iran, Syria, Kuwait and Egypt. But each comprised fewer than a handful of cases. By contrast, the Nigerian outbreak is the largest on record involving vaccine-derived viruses.
The northern Nigeria boycott led to an explosion of polio cases in the country, one of only four still on the WHO's list of nations in which the virus remains endemic. The fallout continues to besiege eradication efforts, both because of ongoing transmission in Nigeria and cases exported to multiple other countries around the globe.

Polio experts say the suspension actually seeded the current outbreak, which involves Type 2 polio vaccine viruses. (There are three strains of wild polio virus, numbered 1 through 3. Ironically, wild Type 2 polio viruses haven't been seen since 1999 and are believed to have been eradicated.)

"We do not see this in southern Nigeria. We do not even see this in Niger. It got just across the border in Niger, two independent importations, two cases, right along the border. It didn't go any further," said Dr. Olen Kew, a polio expert at the CDC in Atlanta, where polio viruses are typed and traced for the eradication program.

"So the population immunity conditions in northern Nigeria are different than in the surrounding areas."

Oral polio vaccine is no longer used in Canada but it is the vaccination tool of developing countries, because of its low cost and ease of administration. The oral drops don't require needles (or safe needle disposal) and don't need to be delivered by health-care professionals.

The vaccine contains live, weakened viruses that stimulate immunity by causing low-level infection in children who receive the drops. And while effective enough to wipe out polio in over 100 countries, it comes with a couple of significant risks.

On rare occasions oral polio vaccine paralyzes children. About one out of every one million doses leads to paralysis.

And the vaccinated children shed viruses in their stools for weeks. Those viruses mutate. If they circulate long enough, the built-up mutations can restore the virulence stripped out in the vaccine production process, giving these viruses back the power to paralyze months and even years after their progenitors came out of a vaccine vial.

It is thought vaccine-derived viruses don't get a chance to circulate long enough to regain virulence in countries where vaccination rates are high and most children have immunity to polio.

Tomori said it is critical that Nigerians understand that it is under-vaccination - not vaccination itself - that caused the problem.

"It is important for people to know that these are the factors, these are the reasons, this is what happens," he said, insisting his country will succeed in ending spread of polio within its borders.

"I have to believe that. There's no other way."


Need a vacation? Get great deals to amazing places on Yahoo! Travel. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

Saturday, September 29, 2007

[vinnomot] Fwd: [Dahuk]: An article to unmask anti-Bangladeshi's and Islam bashers

all should read it  .

Note: forwarded message attached.


Boardwalk for $500? In 2007? Ha!
Play Monopoly Here and Now (it's updated for today's economy) at Yahoo! Games. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___

[vinnomot] Humanism and Ethics: (Comp 2):Assessment of Moral Theories

 
Sacred vs. Secular Ethics: Comparative study of religious, secular, and humanist theories of morality
 
Part 2: Assessment of moral theories
 
So how do we go about evaluating moral theories? It may help to realize that theories of morality are like theories in science. Scientific theories try to explain the causes of events, such as a chemical reaction, the orbit of a planet, or the growth of a tumor. A plausible scientific theory is one that's consistent with all the relevant data. Moral theories try to explain what makes an action right or what makes a person good. A plausible moral theory must also be consistent with all the relevant data. The data that moral theories must explain are what philosophers call our "considered moral judgments" -- moral judgments that we accept after thinking critically about them. Any worthy moral theory will be consistent with those judgments. If it is not -- if, for example, it approves of obviously immoral acts -- the theory is flawed and must be discarded. If our moral theory sanctions, say, the inflicting of undeserved and unnecessary suffering on innocent children, we must conclude that something is very wrong with our theory.
Plausible scientific theories must also be consistent with all relevant background information. A theory about the explosion of a star, for example, must not only be consistent with data regarding the explosion itself, but with facts we already know about gravity, space, heat, light, and scientific measuring instruments. Likewise, plausible moral theories must be consistent with the relevant background information -- that is, with our experience of the moral life. Whatever else our moral experience entails, it certainly involves
1.  making moral judgments
2.  occasionally getting into moral disagreements
3.  sometimes acting immorally.
 
Any theory that suggests that we do not have these fundamental experiences must be deemed suspect. Some popular moral theories do imply that we never experience such things. Their denial of elements of our common moral experience constitutes powerful evidence against such theories.
It is logically possible that our common experience of the moral life is a relative, only seeming to involve moral judgments, disputes, and mistakes. It is possible that the theories that renounce our moral experience are correct and opposing theories wrong. But unless we have good reason to dismiss our experience as relative, we are justified in accepting it at face value. Another way of putting this is that our experience of the moral life is a matter of common sense. Common sense, of course, has been wrong about many things, including the shape of the Earth and the causes of disease. But it does not follow that because common sense is sometimes wrong, it is always wrong. The most reasonable approach is to accept common sense unless its alternative is clearly superior.
The point of having a moral theory is that it gives guidance in choosing the right actions. And the most important guidance is the kind that helps us resolve moral dilemmas -- situations when moral principles or judgments are in conflict. Any moral theory that gives us no help with these problems is said to be unworkable, and any unworkable theory is a poor theory.
So all plausible moral theories must...
  • Be consistent with our considered moral judgments
  • Be consistent with our experience of the moral life
  • Be workable
These criteria enable us to undertake a fair assessment of all types of moral theories -- religious, secular, and humanist.
Five Moral Theories
We can now apply what we've learned to evaluating five different moral theories -- two religious and three secular.
Rule-Utilitarianism
As we noted in previous modules, act-utilitarianism says that what makes an action right is that it maximizes overall happiness, everyone considered. As long as an action maximizes happiness in the world, it is morally correct-regardless of the motives of the people involved or how the happiness is achieved. So doing the right thing means calculating how much happiness can be gained from several possible actions and choosing the one action that achieves the greatest amount of happiness.
We also saw that act-utilitarianism conflicts with some of our considered moral judgments. Certain things should not be done to people even if doing them would produce the greatest amount of happiness. In other words, people have certain rights, and those rights should not be violated just to promote the common good. Is it right to falsely accuse, convict, and punish someone if doing so would result in greater happiness for a whole town of people? If the total amount of happiness of a dozen people could be increased by torturing one of them, is it right to torture him? We usually would consider it wrong to violate people's rights and commit injustices just because happiness might be enhanced.
Finally we observed that act-utilitarianism is in conflict with our understanding of duties. There seems to be no getting around duties that we have to other people, duties like keeping our promises. Act-utilitarianism, however, says that our duty is to maximize happiness-regardless of whether we have to break promises to do it. Breaking promises is just another means to an end. But our commonsense understanding of promises suggests that they are more important than utilitarianism would have us believe. They have more moral weight than some other kinds of statements we could make, otherwise promises would cease to function as promises.
On the other hand, act-utilitarianism does call our attention to something that apparently any good moral theory must take into account: the consequences of our actions. Surely the events that our actions cause can sometimes have moral significance. Absolutist moral theories -- those that would have us follow rules and ignore the consequences -- are in conflict with our considered moral judgments.
So some thinkers have asked, Is there a form of utilitarianism that fits better with our moral life and judgments? Their answer is yes: rule-utilitarianism. This kind of utilitarianism focuses not on how much happiness a certain action can produce, but on how much happiness a certain rule can produce. According to rule-utilitarianism, right actions are those that accord with an exceptionless rule that -- if consistently followed -- would result in the greatest happiness, everyone considered. So to determine if an action is right, you must first ask what rule the action accords with, then ask if following the rule consistently would produce the greatest happiness. Under this theory, it may be right to consistently obey a rule like "don't steal" even if, in a particular case, not stealing may result in the least degree of happiness.
On the face of it, rule-utilitarianism does seem like an improvement over act-utilitarianism, but it too conflicts with our considered moral judgments. It is fairly easy to imagine a rule that, if consistently followed, would maximize happiness in the world -- but would also violate people's rights, cause injustice, or ignore duties. A society could, for example, devise a rule that permitted the killing, torturing, or raping of someone if the act would dramatically maximize happiness overall. In some cases, such rules could sanction mass murder, "ethnic cleansing," and the persecution of every kind of social or racial group. If rule-utilitarianism could allow such actions, there must be something wrong with rule utilitarianism.
In fact, there seems to be something wrong with the whole idea that happiness is the ultimate goal of any adequate moral system. Both major kinds of utilitarianism assume that happiness is the only intrinsic good. But we can imagine situations in which people experience the greatest degree of happiness possible and still seem to be missing some important things that make life worth living.
Philosopher Robert Nozick illustrated this point once in a thought experiment. Imagine that you're hooked to a machine that supplies you with ready-made sensory experiences. You think and feel that you're writing a novel, making a friend, and doing a thousand other pleasant things. But you're actually just floating in a tank while the machine does its work. You are happy, blissful, believing that you are directing your own life and choosing freely all the time. So you stay hooked up for life.
Does this scenario really sound like the good life? Tank life doesn't seem to be utopia at all -- but a kind of hell. Being happy is just not enough.
Ten Commandments Theory/Islamic Shariah Theory
Some people insist that the Ten Commandments/ Decalogue, or Islamic Shariah is the sum total of their morality, a self-contained moral code that needs no additional theoretical underpinnings. (There are many others who say that the Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah rules are just guidelines that help us fill out a larger moral theory.) The question is, is this theory plausible?
The first thing to note is that the Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah theory (TCT) is a type of religious theory of morality called the divine command theory (DCT). This is the view that an action is right if Allah or God commands or wills it. In other words, certain actions are right or wrong only because Allah or God says they are, for he is the author of the moral law. Both religious people and secularists (such as Jean Paul Sartre) have expressed the idea in this bizarre way: If there is no Allah or God, everything is permitted ; as if there was no ethics or morality before the concoction of the idea of Allah or God! The fact is otherwise : Ethics and morality have existed since the begining of human social groupings. Religions, or Allah, God or Yahveh, had never invented or started any morality or ethics. On the other hand, Ethics and morality have existed before the religions and the religions had always included the ethics and morality of their time into their message. No religion was ever ahead of its time in matter if ethics and morality…. !
The TCT/Shariah theory is a legalistic version of the divine command theory in which Allah/God's commands are spelled out in rules stated clearly in scripture or made plain in nature. Another version of the DCT says that Allah/God's commands are expressed not in a set of unbendable rules, but in the dynamics of each moral situation. Christian ethics, though it can take many forms, is usually construed as a type of DCT in which the commandments are those of Christ's teachings, especially of the injunction to "love thy neighbor." Similarly Islamic Shariah is usually constructed from the edicts of Quran and Hadith ; added to these are 9 different factors like Imams (earlier main scholars), collective opion of the Muslim scholars, Doctrines of the different Schools of Thoughts, ; and Mullahs Farwas, etc.
Now, if the divine command theory is unfounded, so is the Ten Commandments theory or Islamic Shariah theory. And the DCT is in trouble. The main problem is that these are not consistent with our experience of the moral life. We can ask this troubling question: Are actions right (or wrong) because Allah/God says they are, or does Allah/God says they are because these actions, just are right (or wrong) on their own right? If the DCT/Shariah is correct, then what Allah/God says goes. If he says that torturing innocent children is right, then it is right. If he says that raping and killing your neighbors is right, then it is right. But this notion of morality is absurd. Our experience of the moral life suggests that some actions are wrong, and it is implausible that wrong actions could become right just because Allah/God commands them to be so. Many religious thinkers have rejected the divine command theory on these grounds.
A proponent of the DCT could respond to this argument by saying something like this: Allah/God could never command such evil acts because Allah/God is all-good. But to say this is to argue in a circle and undermine -- not strengthen -- the divine command theory. The theory is supposed to tell us what morality is, or what makes something good. But if goodness is a defining property of Allah/God, then Allah/God cannot be used to define goodness. Such a tack would result in an empty definition of the DCT: Good actions are those commanded by an all-good Allah/God. Contrary to appearances, this assertion actually tells us nothing about what makes something good.
Some people might contend that even if the DCT is unsupported, we still should do what Allah/God commands because he will reward us for obedience and punish us for disobedience. But this view quickly crumbles into ethical egoism, insisting that we ought to do what is in our own best interest, namely, to seek reward and avoid punishment. But as we have seen, a theory of morality built on self-interest is not much of a theory.
Another serious problem with the TCT is that it conflicts with our considered moral judgments. As we noted, the Commandments/Shariah-rules are absolutist -- they allow no exceptions. A rule is a rule, says the TCT, and the impact that following the rules might have on a person's well-being must not be taken into account. Say a terrorist steals a nuclear device and threatens to blow up a major city, killing millions of people. And the only way to stop this catastrophe is for you to break the commandment against killing and murder the bomber. According to the TCT, killing the terrorist -- even as a means to save the city -- would be wrong because the Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah  forbid such actions. But this view seems unsupportable.
The news about the TCT gets worse. The Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah theory -- like all moral codes -- is unworkable. Moral codes have sets of rules that are inherently vague. They therefore cannot offer much help to people who need specific answers on specific cases. The Commandments/Islamic Shariah says "honor thy father and thy mother." But does this mean that children should honor their parents even if their parents abuse them? What if the father or mother is criminally insane? Does the rule apply to stepfathers? foster mothers? the parents of test-tube babies? The intent here is just not clear.
In addition, plausible moral theories are supposed to help us resolve moral dilemmas, but the TCT (like other moral codes) cannot do this. When two commandments/Shariah-rules conflict, there is no way to remove the conflict without appealing to a moral theory that is outside the scope of the Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah. We're commanded not to kill and not to steal, but what if the only way to avoid killing someone is to steal? Or what if the only way to avoid killing a hundred people is to kill just one? We're told not to bear false witness, but what if by bearing false witness we can save the lives of a thousand innocent people? The Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah gives rise to many conflicts like this -- but can't resolve them. These failings make the TCT a poor theory of morality.
Kant's Theory of Ethics
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) proposes a grand nonnaturalistic theory whose influence is felt to this day. He explicitly rejects the idea that morality is based on natural properties such as human happiness, pleasure, welfare, or survival. He argues that these properties are not our highest good, for they are not intrinsically valuable (good for their own sake). The only thing that is intrinsically valuable is a "good will." A "good will" is the motivation to perform our duty for its own sake -- to act out of respect for our moral duty, not out of regard for the impact that our actions will have in the world or even out of feelings of compassion or love. For Kant, right actions are those performed from a sense of duty for duty's sake.
Kant says that we come to know our duty through reason. All of our duties are derived logically from a single principle, what Kant calls the categorical imperative. (It is an imperative because it commands us to do something, and it is categorical because the command must be obeyed under all conditions.) He maintains that we know this principle a priori -- that is, without experience in the real world, just as we know many truths of logic, such as "whatever has a shape has a size." He thus builds a moral theory that is both nonnaturalistic and nonreligious.
Kant produced two formulations of the categorical imperative. The first one says, "Act only on that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it should become a universal law." That is, act only on those moral principles that you could rationally want to become a moral law that applies to everyone. According to Kant, whenever you perform an action, you are implicitly acting according to a moral principle. To determine whether an action is your duty, you must ask yourself what would happen if the principle under which you are acting became a universal law, or became universalized, and everyone followed it. Would the world you envision be possible? Would it really make sense to want the principle to become universal? If the answer is yes, then you should act according to the principle. If the answer is no, then the principle is not acceptable.
SIZING UP THE GOLDEN RULE
The Golden Rule (usually stated as "Do unto others as you would have them do unto you") has a long history. Confucius may have been the first to spell it out. Some see the Golden Rule in Kant's moral theory: treat others never as a means but as an end in themselves. But many other moral theories -- especially formalist theories -- incorporate some notion of respect for persons, which is the idea at the heart of the Golden Rule.
So the Golden Rule seems to be a plausible -- and respectable -- component of moral theories. But how does it measure up as a stand-alone theory? Some people assert that the Golden Rule is their moral theory with no other elements necessary.
Alas, as a self-contained moral theory the Golden Rule has a big problem: it can lead to actions that conflict with our considered moral judgments. Unfortunately, it is possible to follow the Golden Rule in every case -- and still commit heinous acts.
For example, a terrorist with a death wish might decide that he will exterminate the human race -- including himself. He follows the Golden Rule: he will kill all humans just as he would like humans to kill him. Or say a Roman Christian Nazi fanatic lives by this principle: I will kill all Jews, just as I would want them to kill me if I were a Jew.
Suppose that you stole a car and thus the principle on which you acted is "take other people's possessions whenever you feel like it." The question then is would it make any sense for this principle to be universalized? Note that if it were a universal law, and everyone behaved accordingly, the idea of people owning things would cease to have any meaning. Nothing would really belong to anyone. So the principle itself would not have any meaning. It would not make sense. So you could not rationally want the principle to be a universal law.
By applying the categorical imperative in this way, Kant derived several categorical duties -- duties that have no exceptions in any circumstances. These include the duty not to kill innocent people, not to lie, and not to break promises.
Kant's second formulation of the categorical imperative is "Act in such a way that you always treat humanity...never simply as a means, but always at the same time as an end." This famous dictum seems to capture something essential in moral theories -- respect for persons. We should not treat people simply as a means to an end -- we should not use them as though they were tools. We should treat them instead as ends in themselves, as things valuable in their own right. Kant's view is that people are inherently valuable because they are self-conscious, rational, and free to make their own choices. Thus, it is wrong to steal money from someone because that would be treating them merely as a means to financial gain. It is wrong to lie to people because that would be manipulating them for someone else's own purposes. It is wrong to enslave someone because that would be using them against their will for the benefit of others.
This notion of respect for persons resonates with humanists. Some might even argue that the view that humans are intrinsically valuable is the core idea in humanist thinking. But the idea is not a basic principle in Christian/Islamic morality where humans are merely creature and tools of Allah/God, for each person is thought to be of infinite value only because the divine grace . Kant, however, has probably done the most to show that respect for persons, as sovereign and independent humans, is crucial to morality and that the principle can rest on solid footing.
Kant's theory has some advantages over utilitarianism. The main one is that it sets strict limits on what can be done to persons. No matter how much happiness could be gained in the world, there are certain acts that should never be committed against persons because they are persons. Because persons are intrinsically valuable, they have moral rights -- and these rights cannot be overridden by considerations of utility or the common good.
But Kant's theory may also be flawed. The duties derived from the categorical imperative are themselves categorical -- they have no exceptions. As in the Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah theory, Kant's moral duties must be honored no matter what. In Kant's view, you should not lie -- not even if the lie could save a dozen lives. You should never kill an innocent person -- even if such killing could avert the deaths of a million other innocent people. But this notion of categorical duties is problematic because there do not seem to be any such duties. We have duties, but none seem to be categorical. We can always envision possible scenarios like those above in which honoring a categorical duty would be wrong. Along the same lines, there seem to be cases in which we should treat persons merely as a means. Wouldn't we think it morally permissible to lie to someone -- use them as a means -- to prevent World War III by some monkey-mind politician like the former Cocaine addict George Bush of the USA?
Kant's theory ignores the consequences of actions. In our commonsense moral experience, the effects of our acts do seem to matter to our moral judgments. Utilitarianism may put too much weight on consequences, but Kantian ethics gives them no weight at all.
Finally, Kant's theory is unworkable in its classical form, yeti t is better than Ten Commandments and Islamic Shariah. Many duties can be derived from the categorical imperative, and sometimes they are in conflict. It is possible, for instance, that keeping a promise could cause the death of an innocent person. It's conceivable that to keep your promise to visit a friend in the hospital you ignore the pleas of a seriously injured person you could easily save, resulting in the injured person's death. A good moral theory would give us guidance on how to resolve these conflicts, but Kant provides no such guidance. In fact, he seems to have thought that conflicts among duties could not even occur.
However, if modified in the light of these objections and in according to the realities of our new age, Kant's theory could prove to be an excellent Code of Ethics.
The Ethics of Love
Some people have adopted the Ethics of Love theory (ELT), which says that right actions are those that are based on love toward others. All other moral principles and all our duties are supposed to be derived from this one proposition.
This theory can have either a religious or secular formulation. The religious version is summed up in the Bible, Matt. 22:37-40, which commands us to "love the Lord thy God with all thy heart" as well as "love thy neighbor as thyself"; similar texts are found in Quran and other religious texts. Here the imperative to love extends to God as well as to humans. This kind of ELT has been called agapism (from the Greek word for love), and it has been very influential as a façase in the Judeo-Christian tradition. The secular version omits the injunction to love Allah/God and emphasizes the obligation to love humankind, which means that the secular type of ELT can be a humanist theory of morality.
One appealing form of ELT contains a strong element of situationalism, the notion that moral judgments cannot be based on rules but on the dynamics of each situation. Situation ethics is the general term for moral theories based on situationalism. The idea is that each situation is a separate and unrelated state of affairs in which we must confront the unique set of facts and ask what is the most loving action possible under the circumstances. There are no legalistic mandates -- just the ideal of love and perhaps some rules of thumb ; however, Christian imperialists and missionaries have been killing and mass-murdering as well as enslaving humans of the 3rd world colonies, on the name of Love for Christ and humans : they do favour on the Third world people by enslaving and killing them for love of Christ and for saving the victim's souls while killing their physical bodies… ! Similar Christian love was shown by the very loving Roman catholic and Roman protestant Christians under Hitler against the Jews and liberal Europeans.
The most notable proponent of situational agapism is Joseph Fletcher, who asserts that love is the only universal good. His theory is immature and emotive but attractive to many because it opposes ethical legalism, the idea that morality is based on adherence to a set of laws or rules. The Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah theory is a form of ethical legalism.
Is the ethics of love a good theory? Loving others certainly seems to be consistent with our considered moral judgments. Some ethicists argue that we have a duty to act lovingly toward others -- especially toward those who have acted lovingly toward us. But how much guidance can a vague idea like love gives us when we are faced with moral dilemmas, when we find ourselves in situations that require us to make tough moral judgments? The answer is, unfortunately, not much.
The injunction to love cannot tell us how to act or what rule to follow or what path to choose. The issue of euthanasia is a good example of the problem. Let's say your mother is terminally ill, suffering terribly -- and begging you to put her out of her misery. Because you love her, you want her to be free of pain, to be free of disease, to live. But what guidance can the ethics of love give you here? Should you do what your mother asks and kill her? Should you refrain from killing her? Should you grant her wish -- or ignore her wish?
Or say that you're a doctor who must decide which person among one hundred desperate patients will receive a life-saving organ transplant. You care about every patient, but only one can get the transplant. The rest will probably die. To whom should you give the transplant -- the five-year-old girl because she's the youngest, the middle-aged man because he's in the greatest pain, the thirtysomething man because he's your best friend, or the medical scientist because her research could one day save many lives?
Love may indeed be part of any good moral theory, but the ELT itself is unworkable. And situation ethics theories suffer from the same problem -- even those theories that replace love as the guiding ideal with something else such as humanism or virtue.
Contemporary Intuitionism
When we assess the truth of a moral theory, what kind of evidence or grounds are we appealing to when we refer to our ordinary moral experience or our considered moral judgments? We surely are not pointing to any empirical fact or to a premise in a chain of reasoning. We are appealing to what philosophers call our "moral intuitions." In philosophy, "intuition" refers not to hunches or gut feelings, but to rational knowledge or insight that is not based on mere perception or argument. We know intuitively, for example, that 2 + 3 = 5 or what the concepts "near" and "far" mean. A moral intuition is one concerning moral concepts or propositions.
In the field of ethics, the appeal to moral intuitions is widespread and well respected. In this Module we have been judging moral theories by criteria which include our considered moral judgments and our moral experience. Philosophers do the same thing. They think that any adequate moral theory must take into account our moral intuitions, and that moral theories that conflict with our intuitions are suspect. They know that our moral intuitions are not infallible, but they also understand that our intuitions usually constitute strong evidence unless proven otherwise.
In the past two hundred years philosophers have put forth several rationalist theories that explicitly depend on our moral intuitions. One of the more influential intuitionist theories is that of the Oxford philosopher W.D. Ross (1877-1971). Unlike Kant, Ross argues that we don't have just one duty (the categorical imperative) from which all others are derived -- we have several distinct and separate duties. We recognize these duties, he says, in the same way that we recognize mathematical or logical truths -- through our rational intuitions. Our intuitions, he says, reveal our duties to be self-evident. A self-evident proposition is one in which, if we understand it, we are justified in believing that it is true. As Ross says:
« That an act qu (in the caoacity of) a fulfilling a promise, or qua effecting a just distribution of good...is prima facie right, is self-evident; not in the sense that it is evident from the beginning of our lives, or as soon as we attend to the proposition for the first time, but in the sense that when we have reached sufficient mental maturity and have given sufficient attention to the proposition it is evident without any need of proof, or evidence beyond itself. (Biblio) »
As we have seen in the case of the Ten Commandments/Islamic Shariah theory, if we have several discrete duties, there are bound to be conflicts among them. Ross tries to solve this problem by establishing a kind of hierarchy of duties. He makes a distinction between two types of duties -- prima facie and actual. Prima facie (apparent) duties are those that we are obligated to perform in every situation unless there are special circumstances that provide an exception to the rule. The special circumstances are cases in which prima facie duties conflict. For example, "Do not steal" is a prima facie duty, and so is "Don't harm others." These duties would conflict, for example, if the only way you could keep from seriously harming several people would be to steal something. An actual duty is one we should perform in a particular case after we take into account any conflicting prima facie duties -- that is, after we decide which prima facie duty is most important in the situation. An actual duty is our final duty.
Ross's prima facie duties include
  • duties of fidelity (keeping your promises, honoring your contracts, telling the truth)
  • duties of justice (dealing fairly with people)
  • duties of beneficence (benefiting others)
  • duties of gratitude (compensating others for acts of kindness)
Ross's theory seems to accord well with our moral intuitions about duties, including our sense that some duties must override considerations of the consequences of actions or of the common good. But as it stands, his theory is unworkable -- it provides little guidance for resolving conflicts among duties. The distinction between prima facie and actual duties is some help, but it is not enough to show us how to rank prima facie duties in importance.
Many philosophers find that the most objectionable aspect of Ross's theory is not its workability but its key notion of moral intuitions. Critics have taken Ross to hold :
1) that we have a mysterious faculty of mind that delivers up the Rossian moral intuitions, and
(2) that our moral intuitions yield "certain knowledge" of moral principles. In light of what is known about epistemology and the philosophy of mind, both of these assumptions seem implausible.
Contemporary intuitionists, though, agree that (1) and (2) are questionable and maintain that there are far more plausible forms of moral intuitionism. They argue that our moral intuitions need not be any more mysterious or implausible than the moral intuitions that we ordinarily appeal to. A more credible view of moral intuitions is that they can be self-evident without being infallible; that they can avoid arbitrariness because they involve reflection and can be tested against the demands of a moral theory; and that they are not mysterious because they arise in the same way that other kinds of rational intuitions do -- from an understanding of the concepts and properties involved.
Philosopher Robert Audi, a contemporary intuitionist, explains the more modest claims of modern intuitionism:
« In these forms, I suggest, ethical intuitionism is, in outline, the view that we can have, in the light of appropriate reflection on the content of moral judgments and moral principles, intuitive (hence non-inferential) justification for holding them. Most of the plausible versions of intuitionism also endorse a plurality of moral principles (though Moore is notable for holding an overarching, ideal utilitarian principle of right action), and most versions are also rationalist, holding that there are a priori (present beforehand) moral principles. But an intuitionist could be an empiricist, taking intuition to be capable of providing an experiential ground for moral judgments or principles. Intuitionists typically hold that moral knowledge as well as moral justification can be intuitive, but the major ones are not committed to the view that this justification or knowledge is indefeasible, and then tend to deny that it is.  (Biblio) »
While arguing for such an understanding of moral intuitions, some philosophers have tried to improve on Ross-type theories by providing ways to resolve conflicts among duties. One suggestion is to use Kant's categorical imperative as a formula for weighing competing duties. For example, if a duty to tell the truth conflicts with a duty to not harm others (as when a madman intent on murdering your friend asks you where your friend is), the deciding factor may be whether your choice could be universalized.
Another proposal is to use our moral intuitions -- specifically, our duties to promote good consequences, respect persons, and care for those who care for us -- as criteria for judging the correctness of our actions. Scientists use certain criteria to judge the adequacy of scientific theories (criteria such as how simple a theory is or how many phenomena it explains). Likewise, we could use our core set of obligations as standards for judging actions. This view rightfully assumes that these criteria cannot be ranked in order of importance. But they can render a choice between actions as objective because the criteria do not depend on anyone's mental states.
Such intuitionist views (with some way of resolving conflicts among duties) have several advantages over all the other theories we have examined. They accord well with our considered moral judgments and moral experience and give appropriate emphasis to moral intuitions. They are not hampered by a utilitarian blindness to duties or the rights of persons. They avoid the problems of Kantian-type categorical duties. And they can accommodate considerations of the consequences of actions.
In any case, note that intuitionist theories require no religious trappings. Our moral intuitions seem to work fine without any reference to a supreme being. And because intuitionism by definition is regulated by our considered moral judgments and moral experience, it can easily be adopted by humanists. 
Summary
We have seen that whatever form a theory of morality takes, it cannot be thoroughly absolutist, as religious theories are. Consideration of the consequences of actions is an important part of making moral judgments. But there is also more to moral judgments than calculating consequences, for some actions should not be performed even if they result in greater happiness. So we have good reasons to believe that any adequate moral theory must be a mix of consequentialist and formalist factors.
In addition, we have learned that good moral theories shouldn't conflict with our commonsense understanding of rights, justice, or duties. And they should be sophisticated enough not to assume that love and happiness alone are all that the good life requires.
But what have we discovered about religious and secular moral theories? For one thing, the element of religion or theism in moral theories is simply not sufficient by itself to make the theories worth embracing. Some highly suspect theories happen to be weighted heavily with religion or the supernatural. Likewise, the secular aspect alone is not sufficient to make moral theories plausible. Some secular theories fail miserably. Finally, some theories can be secular yet strongly nonhumanist. They may jettison religion, but also engender a lack of respect for the well-being, rights, and dignity of humans which only a truely Humanist theory can ensure.
 
 If you have missed any part in this serie: Humanism and Ethics or other series: Humanism and Science, NGO activism,Defining Humanism;; please read these at: http://groups. yahoo.com/ group/humanist_ international/ messages
 


Take the Internet to Go: Yahoo!Go puts the Internet in your pocket: mail, news, photos & more. __._,_.___

Your email settings: Individual Email|Traditional
Change settings via the Web (Yahoo! ID required)
Change settings via email: Switch delivery to Daily Digest | Switch to Fully Featured
Visit Your Group | Yahoo! Groups Terms of Use | Unsubscribe

__,_._,___